Showing posts with label Books. Show all posts
Showing posts with label Books. Show all posts

Saturday, September 26, 2015

Journey Toward Justice 24

This chapter is titled 'The Structure of Social Justice Movements.' Injustice can be meted out to an individual by another individual, but it can also be in the form of one community towards another community over a long period of time. In the latter case, removing injustice gets complicated and oftentimes it takes times too. But history has shown that injustice of such sort has been addressed. Addressing injustice at social level take three stages, generally speaking. First, it involves identifying the victims. Laws may be discriminatory towards certain group of people or it could be public practice or perception. Whatsoever, identifying the victims comes as a first step. Second, it involves responding the situation emotionally. Responding must involve emotions because unless people come up with 'this must not continue anymore', it is unlikely to generate social change. Third, it involves activation, which is to critique the ongoing practice or analyse the source of such practice and then critique. Critiquing this way may generate social conflict because those who perpetuating the practice may not want to change their way of functioning or those who are enjoying power at the expense of the victim may not want to give up power. Given that a social change is required, oftentimes this may generate hostile conflict. 

Of course, Nick mentions that not all the social justice movements may follow this pattern in exact sequence. But then it's fair to generalise the pattern! 

Saturday, September 5, 2015

Journey Toward Justice 19

The title of this chapter is 'Does Scripture Imply a Right Order Conception of Justice?' There was a brief discussion on the difference between right order conception of justice and inherent right conception of justice in chapter 5. In this chapter, Nick gives little more detail between the two. 

Ambrose, Basil and John all based their idea about rights in the Scripture/Bible. They believed that human person possesses certain sort of natural right. Well, proponents of right order conception of justice as well as inherent right conception of justice can both endorse natural right; the difference lies deeper. Nick does not say this, but it seems to me that he is implying that whether Ambrose, Basil and John were all in the former camp -- right order conception of justice -- or in the latter camp -- inherent right conception of justice -- one cannot ascertain; they were not providing a theory of justice and they all assume natural right, which both the camps can endorse. The question, however, is which view fits better with that idea which is explicitly or implicitly there in the Scripture. 

But before a note on the difference between the two conceptions of justice. The former camp holds that having a dignity is not enough to generate right; there has to be an external agent that confers right to a person. This right could be natural right! The latter camp holds that being a human generates certain right. The former camp would say something to the effect that a captain in the army has right to issue command because he has been conferred authority/right to issue command; without an external agent having conferred that authority/right, he would have no right to command and even if he commands, it would mean nothing if he was not given the authority/right to issue command. The latter camp would say to the effect: of course, that example holds true there; but take other instance. Does a parent have authority/right to issue command to her child because of being conferred the position/status by an external agent? No. Does God have authority/right to issue command to human kind because he has been conferred the position  by an external agent? No. God has that right to issue command by virtue of being the creator; and that right is inherent right. 

Nick does not develop an account of inherent right of a human person here; possibly he will do that in later chapter. But his account shows that God has inherent right. And this plausibly suffices to show the inadequacy of right order conception of justice who would insist that rights always must be conferred by an external agent. After all God does not need to be conferred right to possess a right; the right in inherent! 

Tuesday, August 18, 2015

Journey Toward Justice 13

This chapter is titled 'On the Claim that Justice is Supplanted in the New Testament'. Nick states that there are those who argue that justice is supplanted by love in the New Testament Bible. One group says that God is concerned about justice but to bring justice in the social order is not our business; God will eventually do that in his time. We just have to wait for now. Another group states that what New Testament really teaches is to love our neighbour, to be benevolent or compassionate. Nygren and Kierkegaard belong to this latter category. Nygren underscores that New Testament is all about love and we should go to all extent to seek the well-being of others. Justice is not the point. Of course, sometimes love may 'perpetrate  injustice', but fine; just love. The came Reinhold Neibuhr who says that New Testament does teach about love. But then try saying 'we love you, Hitler; no killing, please.'; It won't work. Neibuhr says that there are really bad people out there and therefore love alone will not work on this earth. Justice must also be pursued. 

Wednesday, August 12, 2015

Journey Toward Justice 6

There are different sorts of reasons given against rights-talk; against the language of rights being employed to talk about fairness in the society. One of the main arguments against rights-talk, as Nick sees it, is that this sort of thing amounts to strong sense of individualistic thing. 'My right' 'my right' 'my right' kind of thing conveys a sense of individualistic thought. Nick concedes that this might be there, but then the fact that this is there does not mean that we throw out the whole concept of rights. If we throw out the whole concept of rights, this would be throwing the baby with the water. What is the required is that where there is wrong employment of the concept or where there is abuse of rights language, there needs to be correction. After all many social movement like civil rights movement in the US or the movement against apartheid in South Africa and so on employed the language of rights and brought social change, yet they are hardly about excessive individualistic thinking. 

What critics of rights-talk often leave unsaid is what will be lost or what moral category/concept would be lost if this language or concept of rights is altogether discarded. And Nick would venture on to argue that something very key to moral discourse would be lost if this language of right is altogether discarded from our society. Therefore, rights-talk or language of right must continue to be part of our moral discourse. 

Tuesday, August 11, 2015

Journey Toward Justice 5

Nick tells that there are two ways in the West that people think about justice: right order conception and inherent rights conception. Plato's Republic, for example, is the former kind while his (Nick's) is the latter kind. Proponents of the former kind holds that a society is just if it is rightly ordered, or rather conforms to certain principle. Proponents of the latter kind holds that a society is just if people are treated as they have a right to be treated. Nick says that Rawls also falls into this right order conception of justice. 

So Plato's conception is of the former kind and so is Rawls' conception. I fancy that Nick would agree that Mill's conception is also of the former kind and also that of the capability approach especially that which is advanced by the likes of Martha Nussbaum and Amartya Sen; and this would also include the one advanced by Michael Sandel. 

Nick argues that if we look at debates about justice/injustice in the past, those who faced injustice often did not appeal to certain principle to insist that they were wrongly treated; they just spoke about saying that they were denied of their rights and that they were wrongly treated. They were performing their action from the vantage point Nick advances though they may not be developing a theory about it; Nick also did the same thing in the beginning. It was only later that he developed a theory that matches his previous actions. 

This is rather interesting because Nick has argued elsewhere for certain epistemological position which in effects says that there are beliefs (and so actions) that is in us which may not have philosophical ground for taking such a view but over a period of time we come to be aware of such belief and then go on to provide a philosophical ground for holding such a belief. So it's not that philosophical justification/ground always precedes belief; sometimes it could be that belief precedes philosophical justification. 



Thursday, August 6, 2015

Journey Toward South 1

Journey Toward Justice
By Nicholas Wolterstorff
Baker Academic
2013

This is the first chapter of the book. In this chapter Nick tells the story of how he came to believe that he got a call from God through the words of the ones wronged and  that he needs to speak up for the wronged ones. He did not have such a conviction earlier, but after having gone through certain experiences his understanding of things changed. There are two experiences that he tells in the book. 

The first is his encounter of Apartheid in South Africa in a Conference in 1975. In the Conference, he heard and saw blacks and coloured people speaking out angrily about the dehumanising experiences they faced daily due to state policy called Apartheid. The Afrikaners deflected the charge by saying that such a policy was required to enable different people group to maintain their ways of life. They further said that they showed benevolence to these blacks and coloured people by giving them used clothes occasionally, food during Christmas etc. The Afrikaners did not see the issue in term of justice vs. injustice. But Nick saw the issue through the lens of justice vs. injustice. 

The second episode was when Nick was invited for a Conference on Palestinian rights in 1978. He saw and heard from Palestinian themselves about injustice meted out to them. 

Nick asks two questions in this chapter. First, why can't benevolence substitute for justice? Second, why did certain people look into the same eyes, yet not saw the issue as matter of justice/injustice while others saw it that way. Nick defers the answer to later chapters. 

Thursday, June 11, 2015

To Read Book List

In the months to come i.e till April 2016, I wish to have read these books.

1. The Right and the Good
Author: W.D Ross (Philosophy)
Area: Moral Philosophy

2. Political Emotions: Why Love Matters for Justice
Author: Martha Nussbaum ( Philosophy)
Area: Moral and Political Philosophy

3. God and Government
Editor: Nick Spencer (Political Thought)
Area: Political Theology

4. Why Suffering?: Finding Meaning and Comfort When Life Doesn't Make Sense
Authors: Ravi Zacharias (Philosophical Theology) and Vince Vitale (Philosophical Theology)
Area: Existentialism

5. The Fragility of Goodness
Author: Martha Nussbaum (Philosophy)
Area: Moral Philosophy

6. Liberalism and the Limits of Justice
Author: Michael Sandel (Philosophy)
Area: Moral and Political Philosophy

7. The Politics
Author: Aristotle (Polymath)
Area: Political Philosophy

NB: The list is not necessarily arranged in term of sequence.

Wednesday, October 9, 2013

Book Review: Michael Sandel's Justice:What's the Right Thing to do?

Justice: What's the Right Thing to do?
By Michael J. Sandel,
Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2009 ,
307 pages

Michael J. Sandel is the Anne T. and Robert M. Bass Professor of Government at Harvard University where he has taught political philosophy since 1980. In 1985, he was awarded the Harvard-Radcliffe Phi Beta Kappa Teaching Prize, and in 1999 was named a Harvard College Professor in recognition of his contribution to undergraduate teaching. Sandel has also been a visiting professor at Sorbonne University, Paris. A summa cum laude, Phi Beta Kappa graduate of Brandeis University ( 1975), Sandel received his doctorate from Oxford University ( D. Phil., 1981), where he was a Rhodes Scholar under Charles Taylor. He also delivered the Tanner Lectures on Human Values at Oxford University. In 2009 he was invited to deliver the Reith Lectures for the BBC. He lives with his wife and two sons in Brookline, Massachusettts.

The book is based on the course that Sandel himself teaches at Harvard University. Just as much as his lectures draw a huge crowd so much so would the book attract many readers. “Justice” as an introductory book to moral and political philosophy is written to suit the intellectual prowess of an average reader. The writing style is easy to understand; and the philosophical points are well illustrated with anecdotes. The author's anecdotes are composed of real life situation as well as philosophical construct. This is a book not written in a highly academic language, but for average readers who could make sense of what the author was trying to explain. One of the strengths of the book lies in the fact that the arguments of different philosophical persuasion are laid out neatly and logically. The philosophical ideas of Bentham, Nozick, Kant, Rawls and Aristotle were examined and wherever deserved, he gave a clear and gentle critique. It would be fair to concur when Observer observes that Michael J. Sandel is 'one of the most popular teachers in the world.' The book has since then become a classic and is published by Penguin for easier accessibility.

In the utilitarian scheme of things since all human individuals are all governed by the feelings of pain and pleasure they govern us in everything we do and also determine what we ought to do. As community is composed of individuals, government should enact those laws and policies that will maximize the happiness of the community as a whole. The idea implies that in utilitarianism an action is considered to be right or wrong depending on whether it maximises general happiness or not. If an act increases the general happiness it is right, but if an act decreases the general happiness it is wrong. For example, if an innocent person could be killed in a fake encounter and that would avert a communal riot, it would be a right action for the utilitarian. So long as the greater good that would follow outweights the greater disaster that would follow, it is justified to ignore individual rights. Or to take another example that Sandel noted in his book: In ancient Rome, Christians were thrown into lions' den for the amusement of the crowd. The utilitarin calculus would work thus: Yes, Christians would suffer but think of the collective ecstasy of the cheering spectators! But this utilitarian principle sanctioned ways of treating persons that violate what we think of as fundamental norms of decency and respect: the individual human right. This scheme of thinking was first deviced by Jeremy Bentham ( 1748- 1832). Due to the kind of objections that were raised – that it fails to adequately take into account individual's right, and that it reduces everything of moral importance to a single scale of pleasure and pain – John Stuart Mill (1806- 1873) attempted to rescue the philosophical position by introducing qualitative measurement. Yet in the process, Sandel observes, that Mill argued in contrary to what Bentham had been proposing though Mill himself did not quite admit so.

The main proponent of libertarianism, Robert Nozick (1938- 2002), opines that “ only a minimal state, limited to enforcing contracts and protecting people against force, theft, and fraud, is justified. Any more extensive state violates persons' right not to be forced to do certaint things, and is unjustified.” Thus libertarians endorse a very strong version of individual's freedom to choose for oneself, minimising state's interference in framing laws and public economic policies as far as possible. The libertarians oppose three types of laws and policies that states normally enacts: Paternalism, moral legislation and taxation. The argument given was that these laws are illigetimate infringement on individual freedom; in effect, they curtail individual's right to liberty – the right to do whatever we want to do with the things we own, provided we respect other people's rights to do the same. They argue that redistribution of income to effect equality should be left to the individuals to undertake, not mandated by the government. Redistribution of wealth should be a matter of charity by the rich towards the poor via voluntary contribution, not enforced by the law through taxation. “The libertarians sees a moral continuity from taxation (taking my earnings) to forced labor ( taking my labor) to slavery (denying that I own myself).” Sandel takes the far reaching effect of libertarians idea and expose its weakpoints. He narrates a case of consentual cannibalism in a German village in 2001. If we own our lives and may do with them what we please, then imposing ban on consensual cannibalism is unjust; it is a violation of individual's right to liberty. But do we really allow consensual cannibalism in the name of liberty? The fact that most of us would cringe at such crass action leaves a point of weakness in the philosophical principle of libertarianism. The fact that tax is collected by all states underscores that this form of thinking is not widespread. Taxation is important for state to redistribute wealth and oversees people from being exploited or left starving. Without such measure community's life under a state will result in widespread resentment that will eventually affect common good.

Unlike libertarians' celebration of freedom so much so that it permits self-inflicted assault to human dignity such as consensual cannibalism or selling oneself into slavery, Immanuel Kant ( 1724-1804) offers an alternative account of freedom which depends on the idea that we are rational being and is worthy of dignity and respect. Kant did come much before Nozick in term of historical appearance, however, the author has placed the latter's work ahead of Kant in the sequencing of the chapter. In his work, Kant observed that Bentham was only half-right when the latter underscored that we are governed by feelings of pain and pleasure for Kant so thought that reason can be our sovereign master too, at least some of the time. To act with freedom, according to Kant, is to act autonomously, which is to act according to a law I give myself. So if we are enjoying freedom, we must be capable of acting not according to a law imposed upon us from outside, but according to a law we give ourselves. And human reason is that which gives me this law. In Kant's writings, one find two ways that reason can command the will: the hypothetical imperative and the categorical imperative. Hypothetical imperatives use instrumental reason: If you want X, then do Y. Here the reason for our doing Y is because of a condition – to achieve Y. But in categorical imperative, an action is represented as good in itself. It is not something that I do because of the result that could be achieved. To be free, therefore, is when one acts out of categorical imperative, not out of a hypothetical imperative. It this form of freedom that Sandel attempts to explain in the book.

In Kant's political theory, the idea of justice is derived from a social contract as it was found in the idea of earlier contract thinkers like John Locke. Earlier contract thinkers, however, observed that legitimate government arises from the social contract that people decided to establish the kind of principle that would govern their collective life. Kant differed with earlier thinkers by maintaining that the contract was not actual but an imaginary one. The nature of the social contract was, however, never expounded by Kant. It was left to John Rawls (1921-2002) to lay out the nature and content of the contract of the original position. Kant did not lay out a political theory as such. However, his influence on political thought was so far reaching because of his writing on ethical principles.

Rawls' writing emerged during the time when a theory on justice was primarily dominated by the utilitarian scheme of thinking. Moreover, justice as a moral philosophy was not considered so central to philosophical pursuit. With the publication of Rawls' A Theory of Justice so much changed. Rawls brought a tremendous interest and impact in the study of justice. Rawls reasoned thus: Suppose we who are free and rational people, and are concerned to further our own interest, are to deliberate on the kind of principle that would govern our collective life, what kind of principle would we choose? And this principle is to be chosen behind a veil of ignorance, which entails that we have no idea about our status – “no one knows his place in society, his class position or social status; nor does he know his fortune in the distribution of natural assets and abilities, his intelligence and strength, and the like.” And the reason for situating ourselves in this position is to nullify superior bargaining position. Sandel points out that “ Rawls believes that two principles of justice would emerge from the hypothetical contract. The first provides equal basic liberties for all citizens, such as freedom of speech and religion. This principle takes priority over considerations of social utility and the general welfare. The second principle concerns social and economic equality. Although it does not require an equal distribution of income and wealth, it permits only those social and economic inequalities that work to the advantage of the least well off members of society.” Rawls' second principle which is called the difference principle does not require that every member of the society receives equal advantages, but it provides strong incentive to correct drastic unequal distribution of advantages. One of Rawls' main arguments for such incentive is that the gifts and talents that I possess is not my doing. It is rather the circumstances outside of my doing that has brought about such wealth to me. For example, if as a cricketer I earn a lot of money I need to be taxed so that the least disadvantaged could have an improved condition because of this taxation. The fact that cricket is so much in demand at this point of time that made me famous and rich is not really my doing. And therefore I deserve to share the benefit of this outcome with the least disadvantaged too. According to Rawls, what is just and unjust in society is not how talents and fortunes are distributed across individuals but how institutions deal with these differences in the way talents and fortunes are distributed. An institution that would be considered just would be one that takes into account the real differences in human lives and yet distributes the differences to cater to everyone's advantage.

Modern theories of justice usually separate questions of right from arguments about honour, virtue and moral desert. For example, the theories underlined by Kant or Rawls use principles that are neutral among ends, and leave the end purpose to the people to pursue for themselves. This way it gives freedom to the people to choose whatever kind of end purpose they want to pursue. Aristotle thinks differently. Suppose a flute is to be given out. Who should get the best flute? According to Aristotle, the best flute player should get the best flute. Since the purpose of flute is to produce excellent music, the one who can play to produce the best music ought to possess the best flute. Aristotle considers that politics is “about learning how to live a good life...to enable people to develop their distinctive human capacities and virtues – to deliberate about the common good, to acquire practical judgment, to share in self-government, to care for the fate of the community as a whole.” Since political community exists to promote the good life, those who are best in deliberating about the common good should have the greatest share in political recognition and influence. As with flutes, so with politics. Aristotle considered the end purpose of politics is the good life lived because he thought that as a human individual it is in our nature to live in polis and participate in politics and only then do we realize our nature as human beings.

Was there any meaning in contemporary Germany owning responsibility and offering apology for the Nazis' brutality? Was it appropriate for the Australian government to publicly apologize for the cruelty inflicted on the aboriginal people? Is it just to pressure present day Japan to apologize for its wartime atrocities in the 1940s? Moral individualists argue that custom or tradition or inherited status are not the sources of the moral obligations; the only moral obligation is that which one has voluntarily chosen to enter into. This notion of freedom provides no room for moral responsibility for the historic injustices perpetrated by one's predecessors. The sins, after all, were theirs, not mine at all. In the work of Kant when we will the moral law or as in Rawl's when the principle of justice is chosen “ we do so without reference to the roles and identities that situate us in the world and make us particular people we are.” Thinking this way provides no basis for collective responsibility across generations. The implication of the thought pattern will also affect the way one looks at the issue of patriotism, collective responsibility, solidarity and so on. Sandel begs to differ with Kantian and Rawlsian way of conceiving individual's duty and obligation as unbound by any moral ties one has not chosen. The author argues that an individual cannot situate herself outside the community that she is part of. The individual is always influenced by the kind of commonality and cooperation that exists in a community. Thus, Sandel observed that if utilitarianism fails to take the individual self seriously, justice as fairness fails to take the nature of commonality seriously.

To reinforce the point he made, Sandel gave examples. Suppose two children were drowning, and you have resources to save just one. One is your child and the other is a child of a stranger. Which one would you choose to save? Most people would choose to save one's child, and there would require no justification to the question why a coin was not tossed to decide which child to save. In the 1980s, a famine broke out in Ethiopia driving four hundred thousand starving refugees into Sudan. In 1984, Israeli government undertook operation to rescue the Ethiopian Jews. Between 1984 to 1991, Israeli government airlifted twenty one thousand Ethipian Jews to Israel. Most people would not ask why Israeli government did not flip coin to decide who to airlift. It would occur natural that in the two cases mentioned one saves one's child and one rescues one's own people given that there is limited resources. This sort of action could be justified if one accepts obligations of solidarity and belonging. On the contractarians' conception, obligations can arise in only two ways – as natural duties we owe to human beings as such and as voluntary obligations we incur by consent. In the two cases mentioned, the actions could be justified because in each case there is an obligation of solidarity and belongings that go beyond the mere contracts that the contractarians acknowledged. Kantian and Rawlsian way of thinking of the freedom of the self would find it hard to justify why a coin should not be tossed to decide who to rescue. After all in this line of thought there is no responsibility to save one's child or people of one's ethnic grouping since the obligation of solidarity and belongings does not arise as one has not placed under the obligation in the first place.

Kant and Rawls further observed that because we are free and independent selves we need a framework of rights that is neutral among ends, that refuses to take sides in moral and religious controversies, and that leaves citizens free to choose their values for themselves. They refuse to endorse the theory of justice that derive a concept of right from some conception of the good. Aristotle “sees justice as a matter of fit between persons and the ends or goods appropriate to their nature.” Justice is connected to the telos. Aristotle “ maintains that one of the purposes of a just constitution is to form good citizens and to cultivate good character. He does not think it's possible to deliberate about justice without deliberating about the meaning of the goods – the offices, honors, rights and opportunities – that societies allocate.” Sandel summarises Rawls viewpoint thus: “if we are freely choosing, independent selves, unbound by moral ties antecedent to choice, then we need a framework of rights that is neutral among ends. If the self is prior to its ends, then the right must be prior to the good.” Again Sandel argues that this pattern of thinking is mistaken.

Our way of thinking about justice is closely tied to some of the contemporary debates on ethics. For example, on abortion the pro-life believes that abortion should be banned because it involves taking of human life. They argue that they are speaking on behalf of those millions of human being who are unable to speak up for themselves. The pro-choice, however, invokes the notion of freedom and further argues that the law should not take sides in the moral and theological controversy over when life actually begins. They say that government should remain neutral and leave the matter to the women to decide for themselves. Sandel is of the opinion that pro-choice when they consider that they have the right to decide for themselves whether they should terminate the pregnancy or not, they should actually engage with the pro-life on whether the fetus actually bears the status of a human person or not; arguing here that moral and religious ideas should not be invoked is not sufficient. After all both sides presuppose some sort of moral category with respect to the status of the fetus. Similarly, even in the area of same-sex marriage, invoking the idea of freedom is insufficient to justify the practice. The purpose of the marriage has to be debated and discussed to arrive at a meaningful public policy. If government were truly neutral on the moral worth of all relationships, then state should have no reason to ban consensual polygamy or even suicide. And issue such euthanasia would remain virtually a non-issue at all. The fact that we would be unwilling to give consent to polygamy indicates that we don't all the time expect the state to remain netural on moral and theological questions. This entails that we need to debate about the purpose of marriage and other matters which further carries us onto the contested moral terrain where we cannnot remain neutral towards competing conception of the good life. Rawls was, therefore, mistaken to insist that state should remain neutral on moral and theological questions, and must work within a framework of rights that is neutral among ends.

For a secular country in the West, where it is normally considered that moral and religious questions should be kept private and not be brought into public square, the book raises important challenges. As challenging as it is to accept the idea, so much so, if not more, is to live out the idea underlined the book. But the prospect of moral and religious engagement in public square is much more promising than avoiding the issue altogether. Such undertaking is philosophically more robust and is more likely to result in a just society. For a secular country like India where every religious belief is given equal respect and is allowed to practice and flourish, the idea put forth in the book is affirming. In our public engagement, however, general Indians need to learn how to listen and speak forth one's moral and religious position without resorting to any kind of violence or abusive speech. Undemocratic practice cuts short civil and meaningful dialogue in arriving at a substantial public policy for common good. Conducting our social and political engagement with mutual respect is the need of the hour. Engaging in public square freely and openly is unlikely to result in resolving every controversy. However, unless we try we shall never know.

The book covers mainly three approaches to justice: the utilitarians way of thinking that says justice means maximising utility or welfare – the greatest happiness for the greatest number; the second approach that says justice means respecting freedom of choice – either the actual choices people make in a free market ( the libertarians) or the hypothetical choices people would make in the initial condition of equality ( the liberal egalitarian); and the third that says justice involves cultivating virtue and reasoning about the common good of the polis. Sandel did not shy away from making his preference known – the third approach. The book, however, is totally silent on the Marxist concept of class struggle for justice or the different religious viewpoints on the concept of justice. Considering that religion is such a widespread practice or that Marxist ideology has changed the way human soceity reads its history, adding each chapter or two of different religious or intellectual persuasions would make the book more comprehensive. Mentioning the work of non-western thinkers would have been appropriate as well. The capability approach to justice fails to make it to the list too. This approach which emphasizes on the well being freedom of an individual has been there for quite sometime. And it is surprising that this approach to justice is omitted by the author.

In reviewing the work of the utilitarians, Sandel mentioned Bentham and Mill. He left out Sidgwick who probably was the greatest utilitarian. In critiquing utilitarianism, he took two defects of this approach to justice. First, utilitariansm makes justice a matter of calculation. Second, “ by trying to translate all human goods into a single, uniform measure of value, it flattens them, and takes no account of the qualitative differences among them.” One may as well add a third point, which is the problem of measuring the value. For example, it is notoriously difficult to weight the disappointment by a child to whom a promise made is broken against the good done by giving food to a poor family. If one has to be a consistent utilitarian, one has to constantly weight the different options and such effort would make life virtually too tedious. But if the principle is to be scientific as it is claimed, then such challenge cannot be wished away. Sandel's main contention against the liberal notion is that it fails to give a comprehensive notion of freedom, and that state should not remain neutral on the matter of moral and religious controversy. But as Amartya Sen points out in his An Idea of Justice that diagnosing the perfectly just social arrangement is incurably problematic. And yet if the just social arrangment that the contractarians identified is actually flawed, then the philosophical interprise to construct such a just arrangement is going to fail.

The author believes that the Aristotle (384-322 BCE) provides a more comprehensive account of our lives and a more promising basis for a just society. To make such a definite pronouncement is a challenging task. Yet the Aristotelian way of thinking which the author prefers not just underlines the importance of bringing in moral and religious categories into public sphere, but the effect of such engagement entails that if the answers provided by invoking moral and religious categories provides a stronger basis for a just society then state must make law taking into account such moral and religious categories. The author did not go that far to explain how it would look like according to his thought pattern when moral and religious categories are applied in real life issues such as same-sex marriage or abortion. He did say how it may appear to be, but fell short of making a specific conclusion. The advantage of such definite conclusion would make the philosophical position more explicit, though those who disagree with such implication may reject the particular position because of the conclusion. Yet in the intellectual scheme of things one cannot always be a fence sitter; there are times when one has to spell out what one's position logically entails. And I do believe that the author did fall short of making such position explicit at certain point.

One of the major shortcomings of the position Sandel endorses, I would argue, is that it fails to establish the concept of right. Since Rawlsian theory of justice considers right as an important category, it is appropriate to expect a theory of justice that trumps contractarians' position maintaining a robust concept of right and duty. Right and duty are normative social relationships. Without them social relationship will rupture. How to construct a theory of justice that will appropriate the concept of right and duty is different from underlining that right and duty are foundational to human community. The communitarian, a word Sandel would probably use for the school of thought he belongs to, would invoke and believes in the concept of right. Yet, how he would develop the concept within that framework is not undertaken in the book. Is it so because the author thought that the idea of right cannot be established within the Aristotelian framework? May be or may not be. But I assume to the idea of right is an important category and therefore each school needs to defend and appropriate it into its system. The legitimate right claim against me by someone is a claim to my enhancing her well-being in a certain way. This can come about by way of requiring an action on my part or a restraint from action on my part. Failure to treat her as she has a right to my treating her would be to wrong her. The moral condition of my failure to treat her thus is that of being guilty; and her moral condition is that of being wronged. Is it possible to construct such a theory of right within the Aristotelian framework that Sandel endorses? I think not. In the following paragraph I shall argue and explain how within Aristotelian framework the concept is right is undermined.

The Aristotelian holds that the ultimate and comprehensive goal of a human person is that each of us lives our life as well as possible, the well-lived life being the happy life, the eudaimon life. And such a eudaimon life comes about as one lives a virtuous life – virtuous activity is necessary and sufficient for the well-lived life. Right-claim as mentioned above is not always about activity; it could be a passive claim. I have a right to my reputation not being defamed behind my back and without my knowledge. Defaming my reputation behind my back without my knowledge may never affect my way of living; yet it is a right that I have in the life of a community that I live. The right to cast vote can be a virtuous activity that contributes to enhancing my well-lived life. But the right to my reputation not being defamed behind my back and without my knowledge cannot be accounted for in the Aristotelian framework of virtuous activity that contributes to my well-lived life. The Aristotelian eudaimonism can account for only partial right-claim, namely – those virtuous activities which are constitutive of my well-lived life and those conditions that are instrumental in my well-lived life. Those events which do not affect my well-lived life, but to which I have a right to claim cannot be accounted for within the Aristotelian scheme of thinking. Thus to account for fuller conception of right one has to go beyond the Aristotelian concept of happy life. In so far as Aristotelian way of thinking captures the idea of the conception of freedom and civic engagement better so much so the contractarian way of thinking captures the idea of right more comprehensively.

It has been hard to find a theory of justice that can incorporate all the elements and categories into one single theory of justice. Each theory appears defective to some people at certain point. Yet in the Aristotelian scheme of things, it is able to incorporate the idea of allowing every moral and theological position to come onto public square to debate and to discuss freely and without reservation to frame public policy for common good the outcome of the discusson. This is a very strong point for the Aristotelian perspective. After all, for example, to ask a platonic school to come to the public square by stripping the idea of form is to ask the proponent to come with a truncated version of the school. The same applies to a religious community as well. One need not not accept the religious viewpoint per se. However, if religious perspective is more healthy and intellectually more cogent than I see no reason why one should shy away from accepting its contribution. But if religious viewpoint is found to be irrelevant and unhelpful, such ideas can remain within the four walls of the believers. The public square should be a platform that each individual having different persuasion comes forward to engage and exchange idea for human flourishing. States can later incorporate the outcome of the discussion into law and policy. One of the biggest contributions of the book for my personal understanding has been the author's ability to explicate Rawl's work cogently. Compared to other writers in the area of moral philosophy, Rawls writing appears to me to be more difficult to comprehend. Perhaps it has to do with his style of writing. Sandel, however, to his credit has made philosophical work of Rawls and also that of various thinkers very easy to understand. This is a book that students of philosophy as well as Political Science can study and greatly benefit. Guardian aptly sums it up “ One of the world's most interesting political philosophers.” And perhaps one of world's most interesting books on political philosophy too!



Saturday, June 22, 2013

Church, State and Public Justice

Church, State and Public Justice: Five Views
Edited By: P.C.Kemeny
Authentic Books
Page 254

The book presents the viewpoint of five schools on how matters of Church, State and Public Justice should be dealt with. It has the position of the Catholics, Anabaptist, Principled Pluralist, Classical Separation perspective and Social Justice perspective. After each position is explained, the rest of the schools provide comments and thus readers are given good materials to evaluate the strengths and weaknesses of each school.

I picked up this book because I wanted some clarification, and I would say I was provided sufficient information. As a student of theology my interest has been primarily on political theology and eschatology. I am quite aware of the already-and-not-yet tension when it comes to the idea of the kingdom of God. My question was when I pray "thy kingdom come on earth as it is in heaven" how much do I let the aspect of 'already' come into play specially in the domain of political thought. When I read the Anabaptist position in the book, presented by the well-known theologian Ron Sider, I could very well identify myself with him at many point. I thought that used to be me! But even before I came to chapter 4 of Ron Sider, I would say I have found my answer through the writing of Clarke E. Cochran, who outlined the Catholic perspective. One commentator pointed out that Ron Sider's position has a weak concept of the State. I agree. At least for me my understanding of Church-State relationship was at some point fuzzy because I had a weak understanding of the theory of a State. After having read more on Moral and Political Philosophy, I began to wonder how Political Philosophy and Political Theology should relate to one another. And I found that the position outlined by the Catholic position provides the most robust and thought through framework on how a Christian church need to relate with the State. This does not mean that I agree with all the detail in the chapter. In fact Dr. Cochran himself says that not all the Catholics have a uniform position on the finer details. 

Dr. Cochran outlines that Catholic church has four features on how Church and State can relate with regard to matters of public justice: 

Cooperation: This refers to the way the church works together with the government on matters regarding fighting poverty, providing international relief etc. 

Challenge: This takes the form of challenging government policy through agitation, lobby etc.  For example, Catholic Americans  may challenge the policy of the US government to invade Iraq. 

Transcendence: This is about seeking to propagate one's religious belief. This sort of thing transcends the mission of the state, but is part and parcel of being a follower of Jesus Christ.

Competition: This is when Catholic run institution like College compete with government funded institution.

The book would be useful for any Christian student of ethics, political science or political theology. In fact, if people of other religious traditions wish to know the kind of thing that Christians believe, and how the beliefs are applied in political institutions this book may shed light.But non-Americans can skip Chapter 2 which basically is an interpretation of how the framers of US Constitution intended to maintain separation between state and the church.

Thursday, March 14, 2013

An Idea of Justice: A Book Review

Introduction

I endorse what one reviewer says about the author: one of the most influential public thinkers of our time. And I want to add that Prof. Sen is a very modest intellectual figure, a fine human being. One may not always agree with what he says, but it's hard not to admire his honesty and his love for humankind. He's one person I deeply respect and admire! 

 Critique of Rawls
 
The book is a rather thick one – over 400 pages, without the bibliographies. But it's not a deep philosophical treatise that would render the mind of an amateur reader go round and round. But to understand well what he says, I think one needs to have a fair idea of Rawl's idea of justice. It is so because he critiques Rawl's approach to obtaining justice while advancing his view on how a more just society can be obtained. This is how Rawls' idea of justice go about. Let us take a hypothetical condition where members of a certain polity come together to deliberate what kind of principles they would want to govern their collective life. (This is social contract theory). The members don't have ideas about what their ultimate desire in life is or their social and economic status etc. The 'veil of ignorance' has covered their knowledge about their respective social and economic status. This 'veil of ignorance' is applied so that whatever set of principles is obtained by the members in the hypothetical polity, it will be just; no one would be in a position to tailor the principles to suit their individual's interest; all members are equal, and in such equal and ignorant condition, they choose two set of principles:
  1. Each person is to have an equal right to the most extensive total system of equal basic liberties compatible with a similar system of liberty for all.
  2. Social and economic inequalities are to be arranged so that they are both (a) to the greatest benefit of the least advantage, consistent with the just savings principle, and (b) attached to offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity. (TJ, 32)
Rawls contention is that if this set of principles, obtained by way of unbiased deliberation of the members, guide political institution then justice would prevail. Sen challenges this approach saying that trying to identify the perfect set of principles is just not possible. People will have difference of opinion about what right principles or just institution are, and therefore Rawl's approach will not succeed, Sen argues. Sen further adds that people in the past did not agree with themselves about what just society looks like before they proceeded to remove injustice. I don't find this point that Sen raises quite convincing. Because one might say that one can work towards removing injustice, say, slavery while at the same time work to identify the perfectly just institution!

There are two more points that Sen raises as critiques of Rawl's approach, and I think the two points are closely related. In Rawlsian method the deliberation to identify the set of principles takes place within a particular political community, a nation-state. ( Rawls tries to refine this process in his later book Political Liberalism to include deliberation across different political units, but I think it is still problematic). Sen argues that when the quest for justice is confined to just one political unit, even if it's just hypothetical principles, then that kind of principle is not applicable across inter-national scenario; when issues of different nation-states intersect. For example, Sen would ask, how will Rawl's approach deal with the issue of international terrorism? A contract theorist might reply – a sovereign global state will deal with inter-national matters. But since there is no sovereign global state, the problem with what a Rawlsian suggests still persists. UN cannot do the job because it's sovereignty is not like the sovereignty of a nation-state!
 
Sen also raises another problem for Rawls. In Rawlsian method the deliberation of the members is assumed to be taking place within a political unit in an impartial and fair manner. Sen calls this as closed impartiality. How much ever impartial we try to be, Sen argues, we have our own parochialism. No peoples group or region or political unit is free from parochialism. So we need interaction with people outside of our own community to tell us our parochialism and our flaws. Sen calls this as open impartiality. Rawls' approach suffers from what is called closed impartiality; but what we really need is open impartiality. The latter is superior, argues Sen!

Capability Approach

In the capability approach, Sen argues, the three points that he raises against Rawl's method are overcome. But what exactly is capability approach? In Rawls' approach the quest for justice is about setting just institutional structure; whereas in Sen's approach the quest for justice is about enhancing the capability of a person – enhancing the freedom of a person to choose the kind of life a person has reason to value. Rawls talks about liberty, but Sen would argue that liberty is not quite the appropriate category wrt a discourse on justice if a person is unable to go to vote because she requires wheelchair to “walk” and she has no wheelchair nor paved road to “walk”. In this case her capability to “walk” is absent; and so seeking justice needs to consist of enhancing her capability. 
 
For Sen the quest is about capability, not functioning. Let me differentiate the two; and this is a very important point. Let us say there are two people who are fasting: A. Gandhi and G. Mogambo. Gandhi is a political activist and he is fasting in order to seek a change in Army Act; whereas Mogambo is fasting because there is famine in his region. In term of 'functioning' both of them are fasting. However, in term of 'capability' the two are different: Gandhi can give up his fasting and choose to eat whereas Mogambo does not have the choice to give up fasting; he is forced to fast because of famine. Let me also give another example. For a proponent of capability approach what is of concern is whether a person has the capability to vote or not, not really whether one is voting or not. Due to religious reason a person from a religious community like Amish Mennonites may not vote. An Amish Mennonite may choose to vote if she wishes to but in order to respect his freedom of religion, the choice is left open to her. If the concern of a proponent of capability approach is 'functioning', one would have to seek that she votes. However the concern is 'capability' and therefore the choice is left open to her.

 A Brief Remark!

 I think Sen is largely successful is filling the lacunae that social contract theorist leave behind. Sen's approach is simple and yet touches the lives of ordinary people. The book has some repetitive points but I take them to be something which the writer is trying to reinforce his thought. And one great thing about the book is that it is made available at a much cheaper rate compared to many other books published by reputed publishers. What the book does not address is the idea of the good. One might say that because of the fact that people of different philosophical and religious persuasion have different opinions about what the good life is, therefore it's best to take just the 'overlapping consensus', the strand of belief that is common to all the social and religious groups. But can a moral and political philosophy really avoid this subject matter of the good life? Didn't some people group take slavery or infanticide to be a good thing? When Sen argues that substantive freedom must extend even the slaves, won't some people in the 19th century in North America argue back that he must not say anything like that.

The other day Irom Sharmila was produced before the Court saying her fasting amounts to an attempt to commit suicide. Sharmila says that she wants to live, not to die. But she also says that her fasting is against the AFSPA that gives immunity to the army even if the act of the army officer violates the dignity of a human person. As a thinker seeking to influence the public policy, would Sen argue that the Court was mistaken for being concerned with the “functioning” of Sharmila and therefore needs to change its legal position or rather say that it was right for the Court to be concerned with her “functioning”?


But being concerned just about capability, I think, leads a person onto some sort of libertarianism. Should the state ever say this act or way of life of an individual is wrong? If I am allowed to use my capability even to harm my own well-being, where does that lead us onto? So coming back earlier point – Can we really be silent on the idea of the good life in a discourse of moral and political philosophy?

These are some issues I think Sen and his well-wishers must grapple with. Capability approach is still evolving as its proponents admit, and we'll have to wait and see how it evolves further...

Monday, March 11, 2013

What Money Can't Buy: The Moral Limits of Markets (Book Review)

Michael Sandel teaches at Harvard University. The course – Justice: What's The Right Thing To Do? – that he teaches at Harvard is officially put up on youtube for public views. The same course attracts almost a thousand student each year, making Sandel one of the most popular teachers of his generation. 
 
The Kyoto Protocol of 1997 sets binding obligation on industrialised nations to reduce emission of polluting gases. It says that a country can reduce pollution either by reducing emission of polluting gases itself or pay another country to reduce theirs. The second option works this way: US can continue to produce as much pollution as it is provided it pays to replace diesel run buses in India with CNG. After all, the Protocol seems to argue, the effect is just the same: less pollution globally. Let's take another case. Stiffs.com offers “gamblers” a chance to make money by betting on which famous personality will die by year's end. Current “hit list” includes Billy Graham, George Bush Sr., Nelson Mandela, Fidel Castro and others. One may argue that these people are not made worse off when strangers bet on when they will die. Let's take one more case. In 1928 Canada banned walrus hunting except for Inuit whose livelihood depends on that for thousand of years (instead of the term 'Eskimo' which is considered derogatory, 'Inuit' is the politically correct label). In the 1990s Inuit leaders approached Canadian government to sell their right to kill some walrus quota to big-game hunters. The number of walrus killed will remain unchanged; Inuits will get extra money and the hunter their game. The government agreed! 
 
Is the transaction involved in the cases mentioned above morally right or not? Sandel is nonjudgmental on the moral correctness of the several dozens of cases he mentioned. However, he argues that what is right or wrong, what is the good life or what kind of social practices we should prize are some questions we should debate about in public life. Leaving all these questions unaddressed, purely at the mercy of market driven social practices, will render a society virtue-less. Since virtues, generosity or civic spirit grow with use, like human muscles that grow with daily exercise, he asks if maintaining silence on moral and spiritual matters for fear of rival versions competing in the democratic life is healthy. But it is exactly for fear of various moral and spiritual beliefs competing in the democratic market that some people want to keep the subject matter out of the public square.
 
Different cultures practice different moral norms. It was like that in the past; and in the present state of affairs too, that's the case. But does this kind of diversity undermine the whole idea of moral progress? Can we say a culture that practises infanticide is as morally right as a culture that forbids this practice, ceteris paribus. Was it a mistake to abolish burning of widow or slavery because people then thought that such practices were bad? No. They did the right thing. But if they did the right thing then morality is not really relative; or is it? If the idea of moral progress is not a myth then we need to debate moral matters in public square. Unless we do that there cannot be moral progress as a society. Even today some cultures cut off the hand of the thief; some cultures expel couple of same sex; some cultures abort foetus. How must the state respond to the different practices: forget about this matters or debate about them? It's not just economic matters but other ethical inquiries that require debate in the public square, more so in the university settings. Kicking religion and morality out of public square will create an even bigger moral and spiritual vacuum in the political space. 
 
Let me also borrow a line of argument from the book and apply in another setting. In Senapati town and adjoining areas, those who are in a desperate situation borrow money from private lenders at the rate of 60% per year. Sometimes the rate may reach 90% or 120% or even upto 150% per year, depending on how desperate a situation one is in. Proponents of free-market economy would argue that demand and supply matrix engenders such a state of affairs. None compels a person to borrow; the borrowers take loan from the private lenders at his own free will. Based on the demand, supply at such rate flourishes. But one may raise two objections here to such an argument: the fairness argument and the corruption argument. Those who borrow money at such a high interest rate are in a desperate economic situation. Many a times it is for urgent medical care. Charging high interest rate in such a situation is taking advantage of someone's helplessness. So it is not fair (This is the fairness argument). The other argument is that it is a duty of each person to help one another; even the private lenders would agree that the lending of money is to help the needy person, not to exploit him or add more misery to his woes or for profit motive alone. And when interest rate is just so high, the primary concept of lending money to help the needy ones is damaged (This is the corruption argument). 
 
Should we let free-market economy have its way or should we say money can't just buy off one's responsibility, one's duty? May we say that US ought not to trade off its civic responsibility with money? Or in the case of gambling can we say even if one does no harm to someone physically, it is not right to gamble on someone's life – waiting for him to die so that I get paid! Or is this a morally neutral ground that moral and political philosophy/theology must not get into? In this book and in the international bestseller Justice: What's the Right Thing to do? Michael Sandel probes subject matters that sit on the edge of ethics and political economy. With his many real life illustrations and stories, he brings out the moral questions and complexities of human affairs. Sandel is easy to digest yet profound!


Wednesday, August 17, 2011

Few quotes from Vinoth Ramachandra

1. Unless we subscribe to the naive belief that governments do not engage in acts of terror against their own citizens, let alone the civilians populations of other nations, the one-sided use of terrorism by the world's media is baffling. Violent actions by the Israeli army or Israeli settlers against Palestinian civilians are never described as "terrorist," but the term is routinely used in large sections of the Western media for violent acts undertaken against Israelis. Surely journalistic integrity requires that the term terrorism should either be dropped for its vagueness or be used evenhandedly to embrace all organized acts of terror, including those by government. The term militants, guerrilla or insurgent do not carry the same connotations of evil that terrorism does; and hence the hijacking of that term by governments who want to scapegoat those who challenge their legitimacy. ( p. 41)

2. So, a morally and culturally "neutral" state which makes no moral demand on its citizens and is equally hospitable to all cultures and conceptions of the good is logically incoherent and practically impossible. And since every law coerces those not sharing its underlying values, a morally and culturally noncoercive state is a fantasy. Openly recognizing this fact is the first step forward in reconfiguring the nature of politics in any pluralist society. ( p. 143)

2. We all have what has come to be called our cultural blind spots. However rich it might be, no single culture embodies all that is valuable in human life and develops the full range of human possibilities. Only when I am deeply exposed to another cultural tradition and community do I become aware of my own; my imagination is stretched as I am forced to rethink my own in the light of the another way of life, and I come to cherish wha this good and challenge what is bad or ugly. (p. 145)

3. Why are North American or British or German theologies never named as such, but Indian or Latin American or African theologies are? Western theologies are simply assumed to be universal, but non-Western theologies are "contextual." The insularity of most Western theological institutions is astonishing... The only situation in which the typical theology student is likely to learn about other cultures, histories and religious is if he were to follow a course on missiology. In the more academic faculties, these courses do not exist. And in most missiology courses Asians religions are taught in an Orientalist style. Moreover, where chairs of mission or missiology have been established, these studies have become isolated from other parts of the theological task. They became what David Bosch calls " the theological institution's 'department of foreign affairs,' dealing with the exotic but at the same time the peripherical." ( p. 259)

NB: These quotes are from Sri Lankan thinker and social activist Vinoth Ramachandra's Subverting Global Myths: Theology and the Public Issues Shaping our World, published in 2008 by Inter Varsity Press, US. To my friends, I wish to suggest that you purchase the book and read it because it is so good. If you don't have money, sell your coat and get this book! 

You can purchase with debit card or pay when it is delivered from here: 

http://www.flipkart.com/books/0281060231?_l=CJHVEqJO3veuHytbACc9dw--&_r=3QWdvuC3Mw%20wz_dRf_fZmw--&ref=5b142d01-b7b2-4eba-9931-85ddab7cf15d&pid=rsw3f9cd0w

Tuesday, August 9, 2011

From Blaise Pascal's PENSÉES

Our greatness and wretchedness are so evident that the true religion must necessarily teach us that there is in us some great principle of greatness and some great principle of wretchedness. It must also account for such amazing contradictions. 

To make us happy it must show us that a God exists whom we are bound to love; that our only true bliss is to be in him, and our sole ill to be cut off from him. It must acknowledge that we are full of darkness which prevents us from knowing and loivng him, and so, with out duty obliging us to love God and our sin leading us astray, we are full of unrighteousness. 

It must account to us for the way in which we thus go against God and our own good. It must teach us the cure for our helplessness and the means of obtaining this cure. Let us examine all the religions of the world at that point and let us see whether any but the Christian religion meets it.

PS:  Blaise Pascal (1623-1662) was a French mathematician and physicist. Following his 'second conversion in 1654, he left scientific pursuit and devoted himself to writings on religious topic. In honour of his scientific contributions, Pascal is the name given to the SI unit of pressure and to a programming language. Pascal's law, Pascal's triangle and Pascal's Wager too bear his name. His most famous writing is Pensées (Thoughts), and is one of French most eloquent books on prose. It is an examination of Christian religion. He died at 39.

Thursday, January 29, 2009

Top 10 religious books of the 20th century

1. C. S. Lewis
Mere Christianity

2. Dietrich Bonhoeffer
The Cost of Discipleship

3. Karl Barth
Church Dogmatics

4. J. R. R. Tolkien
The Lord of the Rings (trilogy)

5. John Howard Yoder
The Politics of Jesus

6. G.K. Chesterton
Orthodoxy

7. Thomas Merton
The Seven Storey Mountain

8. Richard Foster
Celebration of Discipline

9. Oswald Chambers
My Utmost for His Highest

10. Reinhold Niebuhr
Moral Man and Immoral Society